Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Phonetics and Phonology
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
Teaching Methods
Teaching Strategies
Discourse adjectives are not factive
المؤلف:
GINA TARANTO
المصدر:
Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse
الجزء والصفحة:
P308-C10
2025-05-01
56
Discourse adjectives are not factive
Kiparsky and Kiparsky’s list of factive predicates is presented in (1), and their list of non-factive predicates is provided in (2).
Kiparsky and Kiparsky characterize the class of factive predicates as based on presuppositions in the sense of “propositions that the speaker presupposes to be true” (1971: 147). For them, factivity depends on presupposition rather than assertion. Factive predicates presuppose the truth of their complement. That is, a sentence A presupposes a sentence B if and only if B is true whether or not A is true or false.
It is noteworthy that Kiparsky and Kiparsky categorize clear as a factive predicate. In what follows I show that clear is in fact not factive, though I admit that it has a strong flavor of factivity. Consider the pair of sentences in (3).
Sentence (3) seems to entail that Briscoe is a detective. That is, an initial assumption an addressee may make after hearing an utterance of (3) is that Briscoe is a detective. A standard cancellation test as applied in (3b) shows that the entailment can be canceled, indicating that clear doesn’t entail the truth of its complement proposition.
What have now become standard diagnostics for presupposition as it relates to factivity are that the presuppositions remain constant under negation and questioning. The interaction of negation with factive verbs is illustrated in (4).
In (4), only the emotive reaction to the embedded proposition is negated. The sentences still presuppose that the embedded proposition (here, the proposition expressed by the sentence the door is closed) is true. As a result, overtly denying that the door is closed leads to a contradiction unless the utterance is meant to challenge the appropriateness of the choice of the word odd or regret in a metalinguistic use of negation (Horn 1985, 1989). As a result, overt cancellation of this proposition results in a contradiction, as shown in (5).
The presuppositions of discourse adjectives, unlike the presuppositions of true factives, do not remain constant under negation. Thus, in contrast to the sentences in (5), the sentences in (6) are not contradictory.
With respect to the constancy of presuppositions under questioning, Kiparsky and Kiparsky discuss the example in (7).
When a speaker utters (7) the conveyed meaning is not an inquiry as to whether or not the money is gone. Rather, it takes for granted that the money is gone, and questions the addresseeطs reaction to that fact. Discourse adjectives fail to pattern like true factives with respect to this diagnostic as well. Consider (8).
(8) Is it clear that our money is gone?
While it is possible to interpret a speaker’s utterance of (8) as an indication that she believes the money is gone and is inquiring about the addressee’s reaction to this fact, this is not the only reading possible. That is, (8) is indeterminate between a reading in which the speaker is questioning whether or not the money is gone, and questioning whether or not this is clear to the addressee.